The linguistics of racism
Paper read on 5
July 2005 at a conference of the International Society for Political Psychology
in Toronto, Canada
1.
Introduction
·
Racism
in South Africa is alive and well! That is at least the impression one gets
when one opens a daily newspaper and takes notice of the frequency of the word racism
(and related words) that appear in news and in-depth articles.
·
Ironically,
post-apartheid South Africa is supposed to be ridden from the practices of
racism - especially when one takes into account the fact that the South African
Constitution deals explicitly with the "racism-relevant" concept
equality.
·
But
the essence of the problem lies, in my view, in the formulation of the relevant
articles 9 (3), (4) & (5), reading as follows:
9. (3) The state may
not unfairly discriminate directly or
indirectly against anyone on one or more grounds, including race, gender, sex,
pregnancy, marital status, ethnic or social origin, colour, sexual orientation,
age, disability, religion, conscience, belief, culture, language and birth.
(4) No person may
unfairly discriminate directly or indirectly against anyone on one or more grounds in
terms of subsection (3). National legislation must be enacted to prevent or
prohibit unfair discrimination.
(5) Discrimination on one or more of the grounds listed in subsection (3) is unfair unless it is established that the discrimination
is fair.
·
Although
the principle of fair discrimination is also accepted in other communities, for
instance the Dutch community - in which case it is called "positieve
discriminatie" (positive discrimination) - the essence of the problem lies
in the principle itself, as it is reflected by the adjectives fair and unfair
and the noun discrimination with regard to the practices of racism - but
most importantly, in the way people understand these concepts pertaining to its
linguistic use and its relevant communicative and social practices.
·
Should
semantic criteria be taken into consideration, the adjective fair falls
within the class adjectives of judgement. As such its meaning does not
suggest factuality. Consequently, individual judgement will determine many
different readings of the sense of the relevant word.
·
Another
complicating factor with regard to the adjective fair involves the fact
the experience of its meaning reflects the conceptualizer's moral judgement on
account of a certain fairness metaphorical model (cf. Lakoff & Johnson,
1999:297). With regard to the model of equality of distribution Lakoff &
Johnson (1999:297) rightly illustrates the complexity of the fairness concept
in the following words:
"(T)here
are a myriad of cases in which people generally agree on the necessity of some
procedural rules of distribution, but find at times that following those 'fair'
procedures results in a distribution of goods or opportunities that conflicts
with their sense of rights-based fairness or equality of distribution fairness.
In such cases there is typically no overarching neutral conception of fairness
that can resolve the conflict of values."
·
In
this regard fairness could lead to what Gullestad (2004:187) calls "racism
in the name of the good".
·
Within
the limits of this paper racism in relation to morality can not be dealt with
furthermore. The next section will therefore focus on the parameters of this
talk.
2.
Theoretical framework and structure
·
Against
the background of the above-mentioned principle, I will scrutinize aspects of
the concept racism from a cognitive linguistic view. The analysis will be done
in view of two general theoretical assumptions within cognitive linguistics,
that is:
1.
The conceptualist approach to meaning renders more viable analytical mechanisms
than the language-world approach and the language internal-approach - although
the language internal-approach will be taken into consideration when the
dictionary descriptions of the relevant concept is scrutinized.
2.
Language structure provides important evidence about fundamental mental
phenomena which have general psychological importance, and which are founded on
linguistic evidence, such as force dynamics, image schemas, subjective versus
objective construal, correspondence across cognitive domains, and cognitive reference point - cf. Langacker
(1993:1).
This paper will be structured as follows:
1.
A few dictionary definitions of the word racism will be examined.
2.
A distinction will be made between the words racialization and racism.
Reference will be made to the imprint of racism by virtue of underlying image
schemas and categorizing mechanisms.
3.
The fundamental nature of racism will be scrutinized on account of a prototypical
act of racism.
3. Dictionary definitions of the word racism
·
Departing
from a language-internal approach, an analysis of the definitions of the
word racism from three different dictionaries reveals a rather
complex conceptual structure. In this regard the following observations can be
put forward:
1.
The word racism embraces concepts associated with words like prejudice,
animosity, belief, adherence to, advocacy, doctrine,
program, practice, feeling and action on the
presumption that people are to be differentiated on account of different
characteristics which are manifestations of superiority or inferiority. It is
also assumed that the conceptual contents of words like prejudice, discrimination
and antagonism link with the relevant concept.
2.
It appears that there exists no lexical interrelationship between the word racism
and the associated words, merely because they are not associated on account of
equivalence of meaning (synonymy), or as a result of opposite meanings
(antonymy), nor meaning inclusiveness (hyponymy). [It does not imply that the
relevant word does not belong to other lexical networks.] This phenomenon could
be one of the reasons that in a 2004-research on educator's experience of
racism in education (in South Africa), it was found that 64% of the respondents
in an empirical study abstained from answering the question "What is
racism?" (cf. De Wet, 2004:28). The same research also revealed that 88%
of the 36% who did answer the question, used the word discrimination
(cf. De Wet, 2004:31) to explicate the relevant concept. From a linguistic
point of view, this finding illustrates a basic cognitive principle: we tend to
exemplify (understand) more abstract concepts in terms of more specific
concepts - in this instance an action. In other words: racism is not an
act(ion); but to discriminate is - to be precise, the word racism does
not have a verb correlate, but discrimination has: to discriminate.
Incidentally, this linguistic feature applies to perhaps the most - if not all
- -ism-words, for instance capitalism; communism; socialism;
etc.
4.
Discrimination as a prototypical act of racism
·
The
previous assertion, namely that the concept racism is exemplified by a more
cognitive convenient concept that could be related to an action by way of its
linguistic manifestation in a root verb, is implicitly revealed in most
lexicographical definitions of the word racism - since the phenomenon
'racism' primarily deals with differences. But differences have to be brought
to the fore by an action! From this point of view one could deduct that the
concept discrimination functions on a prototypical level to unveil the concept
racism. This view is supported by the Van Dale (Dutch) dictionary which
considers the sense "discrimination owing to race" as one of the
fundamental lexicographical definitions of the word racism. If this is
the case, a more fundamental investigation should turn the focus to the root,
namely the verb to discriminate.
4.1. Polysemous
senses of the verb to discriminate
·
An
examination of different dictionaries' treatment of the polysemous senses of
the verb to discriminate discloses a rather irregular semantic pattern.
Within lexicographical practice three major ordering patterns exist to arrange
these senses, namely on historical grounds, primary vs. secondary meanings and
empirical analysis (referring to the frequency of the relevant word's use). The
Webster's New World Dictionary & Thesaurus differentiates between
the transitive and intransitive uses of the relevant verb, listing the senses
respectively as follows:
"1 v.t. to constitute a
difference between; differentiate. v.t. 2 to recognize the
difference between; distinguish. v.i. 1 to see the difference (between
things); distinguish. v.i. 2 to be discerning. v.i. 3
to make distinctions in treatment; show partiality (in favor of) or
prejudice (against)."
·
The
Oxford Talking Dictionary follows a similar model; compare:
"1 v.t.
Make or constitute a difference in or between; distinguish, differentiate. E17.
2 v.t. Distinguish with the mind; perceive the difference in or
between. M17. 3 v.i. Make or recognize a distinction, esp. a fine
one; provide or serve as a distinction; exercise discernment. L18. 4 v.i.
Make a distinction in the treatment of different categories of people or
things, esp. unjustly or prejudicially against people on grounds of
race, colour, sex, social status, age, etc. L19."
·
The
Encarta World English Dictionary also distinguishes three senses, but
contrary to the previous dictionaries, it puts the race-related sense first -
consequently, and presumably, the primary sense, according to this dictionary:
"1 intransitive
verb treat group unfairly because of prejudice: to treat one person
or group worse than others or better than others, usually because of a
prejudice about race, ethnic group, age group, religion, or gender. 2 intransitive
and transitive verb discern difference: to recognize or identify a
difference · could not discriminate between red and green. 3
intransitive verb be aware of differences: to pay attention to
subtle differences and exercise judgment and taste."
·
The
Van Dale Groot Woordenboek der Nederlandse Taal (Dutch Dictionary)
distinguishes two senses, and in accordance with the Encarta World English
Dictionary, they consider the race-related sense as the primary one.
"1
discriminatie toepassen ten opzichte van, niet gelijk behandelen de Chinezen
in Maleisiƫ voelen zich gediscrimineerd. 2 tussen twee gelijkende
voorwerpen onderscheiden een microscoop met een uitstekend discriminerend
vermogen."
4.2. First recorded uses of the basic senses of
the verb to discriminate and the noun racism
·
When
we examine, from a historical point of view, the first recorded uses of certain
senses of the words to discriminate and racism, some uncertainty
arises regarding the fact that a race-related sense of the verb to
discriminate should be regarded as the primary one; compare the following
historical facts in connection with different senses, according to the Oxford
Talking Dictionary:
1.
The first recorded use of the word discriminate took place between 1600
- 1629.
2.
The first recorded use of a race-related sense of the verb to discriminate
took place between 1870 - 1899.
3.
The first recorded use of the word racism took place between 1930 -
1969.
4.3. Distinction between the basic senses of
the verb to discriminate
·
The
previous analysis suggests that a distinction should be drawn between two basic
senses of the verb to discriminate. The first sense relates to a
basic conceptual action which determines categorization, something we do when
we become aware of the difference in or between entities,
something we do when we "distinguish with the mind" (Oxford
Talking Dictionary). It is important to notice the use of the prepositions in
and between in this description. In this regard, the verb to
discriminate entails the practice of categorization, the most fundamental
conceptual experience in thought, perception, action and speech, according to
Lakoff (1987:5), explicated by him as follows:
"Every time
we see something as a kind of thing … we are categorizing. Whenever we
reason about kinds of things … we are employing categories."
·
The
second (race-related) sense refers to actions or attitudes with regard to the
prepositions for or against, as described by the Webster's New
World Dictionary & Thesaurus as "show partiality (in favor of)
or prejudice (against)".
4.4. The relationship between the basic senses
of the verb to discriminate and the concept racism
·
The
previous distinction links with different approaches Gullestad (2004:177-203)
discusses with regard to the definition of racism. She examines two
anthropologists' definitions of racism as applied to contemporary Norwegian
society. Relevant for this discussion is the view of Inger-Lise Lien (1996 - as
mentioned by Gullestad, 2004), and the way in which Lien (Lien, 1997 - as
discussed in Gullestad, 2004:185-186) sees it according to Miles' (1989)
definition, differentiating between the concepts racialization and racism:
"While
racialization is a natural cognitive process, racism is a negative continuation
of that process."
·
The
concept racialization relates to the first basic sense of the verb to
discriminate, referred to in the previous paragraph, while the concept
racism entails the second primary sense of the relevant verb.
·
In this respect Gullestad (2004:186) has serious
doubts whether the fact that people merely notice differences (the cognitive
process referred to as racialization, for instance black and white skin
color), can be considered a natural cognitive process. She postulates:
"Interpretations
of differences are not universal, but emerge in historically specific processes
as human beings give meaning to what goes on around them. When some physical
features appear as particularly visible, it is not only due to the features
themselves, but to historically specific frames of interpretation that have
become self-evident and self-explanatory for many people. Visibility, in the
sense of prominent features that are invested with particular meanings, is not
natural and universal but is historically specific and culturally produced and
reproduced through fleeting and shifting negotiations."
·
This
observation relates to MacLaury's (1991:59) viewpoint that the selective
emphasis on the prototype choice (of a category) is determined by
vantage point - therefore also extended to a certain cultural frame; as a
result "(d)ifferent individuals place importance on distinct attributes of
the members of a category. Conse-quently, they select different members as
prototypical, they rank members at different values, and they contract or
dilate a category to different extents." This phenomenon is also evident
when a paradigm (category) is conceptually reduced to such an extent that it
results in stereotyping, "a conventional idea associated with a word,
which might well be inaccurate", according to Lakoff (1987:168).
·
Stereotyping
usually underlies the act of discrimination on a racial basis.
5.
A racial imprint
·
Both
the views of Gullestad and MacLaury tie with one of the fundamental findings in
cognitive linguistics, namely the fact that many (abstract) concepts relate to
image schemas, which are preconceptual gestalts within the cognitive
unconscious. They are acquired by way of our bodily experience of the physical
world we live in. Repeated experiences of related spatial and force phenomena
create these gestalts - gestalts that are linguistically manifested. Compare
how the container image schema enables us to talk of both concrete and abstract
containers: in the box vs. in trouble. One of our very basic
spatial experiences relates to proximity, and the schema that is based on this
experience, is called the proximity schema. In view of the experience of
proximity, one has a closer relationship to comforting entities and
situations, and a more distant relation to discomforting entities and
situations. Taylor (1995:134) maintains that the "degree of emotional
involvement and the possibility of mutual influence are understood in terms of
proximity".
·
Against
this background I want to assume that in a country like South Africa, where an
official (racist) policy of apartheid was created and maintained for almost
fifty years, the proximity schema had an important influence on many
individuals' categorical (group) development. Legislation based on racial
segregation enabled this principle - with its closer to as well as its more
distant experiences - to be manifested in the social lifes of individuals,
to such an extent that one can easily speak of the existence of a racial
imprint in the cognitive setup of both black and white people. The fact that De
Wet's (2004:28-37) research reveals that both black and white people still
experience racism in education, in spite of the stipulations of the
Constitution and efforts to build a non-racial society, in some sense supports
this view. Although, merely judged on perception, one notices a big difference
between the way adults and children accept each other on the basis of race
since 1994. Children of different racial backgrounds tend to be more adaptable,
and although most adults really persist in efforts to maintain good racial
relations, the undertones of racism are very often perceived in potential
stereotyping situations triggered by emotional incentives.
·
The
previous assumption also rests on another basic mental phenomenon, namely the
way in which we construe meaning in a subjectivised or objectivised way.
Children, these days, experience the concept of race in a more subjectivised
way, to such an extent that they are presumably mostly unaware of the fact that
strict conceptual boundaries for the category 'race' could exist. Contrary to
this categorical experience adults' views may still be objectivised in many
instances - in other words they accept, but they are still very aware of firm
differences based on a developed prejudiced view. Such an attitude is very
often revealed by emotional experiences of some kind - experiences that relate
to category membership.
·
The
awareness of race on the basis of the above mentioned experiences relate to the
concepts racialization and racism. Racialization implies a subjectivised
experience of race, while racism entails an objectivised experience of race,
adding (almost certainly stereotyped on account of pre-conceptual schemas)
values to differences.
6.
Conclusion: the concept racism as a conceptual blend
·
To
endeavour a conclusion some of the previous assumptions need to be reiterated.
·
The
concept RACISM implies a conceptual blend of many different kinds of actions.
The primary action that reveals racism, is exemplified by the verb to
discriminate. Examination of the dictionary meanings of this verb
reveals two basic senses:
Firstly, it means to categorize, to apply
boundaries in order to place different kinds of entities in different kinds of
paradigms on account of certain differentiating criteria. Such a mental action
is a normal conceptualizing action.
·
The
second sense involves the experience of another kind of mental action that
blends with the first one: to add a value to the relevant category. Should this
value be based on racial criteria, one could consider it to be a racist intend.
But values as such derive from different conceptual blends from a specific
experiential frame that involves historical, cultural, social, personal and
many other kinds of variables. When Gullestad (2004:186) mentions
"interpretation", she actually merges two conceptual operations:
categorizing is the first mental operation; adding a value to the category
constitutes a next operation. She only mentions the second one.
·
As
was mentioned previously, our ability to categorize is the most fundamental
mental process in order to make sense of the world we live in, or to give
meaning to what we experience. To add a value to a category is just one of many
cognitive (also blending) mechanisms we use to manoeuvre a category
conceptually. Other mechanisms involve, inter alia, establishing the prototype
or prototype schema of a category, determining the resemblance of other
category members to the prototype, and to highlight or weaken the boundaries of
a category.
·
With
regard to racism we can accentuate two variables that determine, in my view,
the degree of racist practice. Perhaps one should rather label racism on
account of this criterion (the relative effect of racism), rather than the
traditional eclectic distinction that is made with regard to the status of the
individuals who practice racism and/or to the context it has an effect on:
institutionalised (structural), non-institutionalised (individual) and cultural
racism. The two views I wish to mention, are:
1.
The way in which one manoeuvres a category conceptually on account of a racial
criterion, determines the degree of racism one practices. Stereotyping is an
example of such a manoeuvre. In such occasions prejudice - perhaps on account
of isolated experiences - may play a dominant role. The outcome in such
instances may be mild or severe, depending on the status of the racist
practitioner or the nature and intensity of the speech act accompanying the
racist intend. Should it be racist legislation, like in the previous apartheid
South Africa, the racist outcome is very harsh. But even without legislation,
stereotyping by a head of state could have a very intense outcome. The way in
which racial boundaries are conceptualized, is another intensifying factor. While
apartheid South Africa was an example of the application of the
strict-boundary-principle, post-apartheid South Africa is not without it. It
can be argued that affirmative action, black empowerment, and even
transformation as such, rest on this principle. If a minister (of sport)
explicitly states that "ethnic blacks" should be the ones who should
be benefited the most, then there is little doubt whether it could be
considered a racist action.
2.
The relative power one has access to, determines the degree of racism one can
practice. Legislative power and the way it is executed would obviously be the
most vigorous mechanism for the itensity of racist practices. Apartheid South
Africa was a good example of such authoritative racist practices - even in linguistic
disguise, using synonyms like the following to give a milder image of the
concept: separate development, pluralism, etc. Judging the views
of different commentators with regard to post-apartheid South Africa, one gets
the impression that in many instances the practice of racism presently goes in
the disguise of words and phrases like affirmative action, black
empowerment, black ethnicity - and even transformation. What
one has to take cognisance of, is the fact that the word used can have a
weakening or strengthening effect on the impression of the action it refers to.
A very interesting phenomenon in this regard is revealing itself presently.
Although the government is predominantly black, and the ruling party (the ANC)
comes from a black freedom movement, and they are the people who have the power
to apply transformation with all its implications, they still accuse white people
of racism, while many white people accuse the present rulers of racism owing to
the discriminating practices of transformation, affirmative action, black
empowerment, implementation of quota systems, creating a work force which will
represent the demographic image of the country, etc. - which they not only have
the power to practice, but which they are allowed to do under the auspices of
the Bill of Rights in the Constitution (as was explicated in the introduction
of this paper). This phenomenon can be explained by the fact that many smaller
domains of empowerment are still controlled by white people - white people who
are still in managerial positions, white people who still have economic and
financial power, white people who still have educational power, etc., although
the public realm is not a white public space anymore (to use the words of
Gullestad, 2004:187).
·
Against
the background of the previous discusssion I venture, in conclusion, the
following model to present a prototypical act of racism on account of the
distinction between racialization and racism.
Figure 1: Prototypical
discriminating act, constituting either racialization or racism
.....................